top of page

Expanding The Logical Foundations Of The Quran (Part 3)

  • Writer: ashrefsalemgmn
    ashrefsalemgmn
  • Feb 11
  • 4 min read

Rules of Inference: Foundations of Logical Analysis


Introduction to Logical Categories


In our return to the foundations of logic, we must consider several key elements. The laws of thought serve as axioms, their application manifests as quantification, and the relations we distinguish within these axioms - that is the relation between the axiom and its application - form our rules of replacement.


Topology in Logical Structures


The concept of topology is characteristically logical. Just as gravity provides a universal framework for physical phenomena on Earth, logical domains operate under specific modes governed by rules of inference. These rules, when examined comprehensively, reveal hierarchical relationships—some rules naturally subsuming others through similarity in structure.


Core Rules of Inference


Rather than mere conventional rules, the rules of inference function as dynamic principles. They enable the classification and organization of logical rules into categories by giving us the fundamental principles from which all other logical rules derive. those principle rules are:


1. Modus Ponens: The Foundation


  • Formal expression: ((P → Q) ∧ P) ⊢ Q

  • Natural meaning: When determining a rule Q, the determination always proceeds from the variable P that represents the logical system as a whole. Rule Q serves as evidence of P's existence—a principle that applies universally to all logical propositions.


2. Modus Tollens: The Inverse Principle


  • Formal expression: ((P → Q) ∧ ¬Q) ⊢ ¬P

  • Natural meaning: This reverse of modus ponens establishes that if rule Q doesn't occur, the rule of which it is the limiting case cannot exist. This principle is essential for defining specific rules as it sets up that condition from which a proposition is made.


3. Disjunctive Syllogism: The Principle of Possibility


  • Formal expression: ((P ∨ Q) ∧ ¬P) ⊢ Q

  • Natural meaning: This rule governs the reproducibility of rules. Consider how this manifests in everyday thinking—your ability to recall any rule or memory mid-conversation functions through disjunctive syllogism. Or how, in an group of things, your can move from one to the other, your basis is not any one definite element, but a basis that's not restricted to any of them.


4. Hypothetical Syllogism: The Systemic View


  • Formal expression: ((P → Q) ∧ (Q → R)) ⊢ (P → R)

  • Natural meaning: This rule governs our general inference of logical rules. It requires an external view of the system, maintaining the appropriate distance that enables recognition of systemic patterns. You recognize in something a characteristic that belongs to something else; you recognize that the fur of some animal is a certain color. You're here using the hypothetical syllogism.


The Metalogical Framework


These rules of inference serve as the foundation for metalogical relations, ultimately establishing the rules of replacement. Rules of replacement emerge as direct modifications of inference rules—we adapt the basic formulae constructed by inference rules to fit specific situations.


Quantification and Rules of Inference


Understanding rules of inference requires quantification. When applying a logical rule like distributivity, we invoke not just the rule itself but all underlying principles. Quantification acts as a conductor, instantiating rules of inference in practical applications.

Consider Kant's definition of judgment (Urteilskraft) as "the faculty of thinking particular under the universal." This aligns perfectly with quantification—both describe the same cognitive process, though quantification emerges from mathematical thinking and carries with it mathematical presuppositions.


Rules and Truth Dispositions


Rules of inference define our orientation toward concepts of truth and falsehood. Quantifiers, meanwhile, govern our immediate, spontaneous judgments within these rules. When we assert "x is true, we mean 'every way' in which x may appear; validating, at one stroke, all x - positions (expositions)


  • (x → y)

  • (y → x)

  • (x → x)

  • x(x → y)


This systematic approach to logical rules reveals their deep interconnection and their role in structuring all rational thought.


Note: The symbol ⊢ represents logical entailment, indicating that the conclusion necessarily follows from the premises.


Quantification and Concepts of Space: A Philosophical Analysis


The Nature of Spatial References


Consider our fundamental spatial references: up, down, left, and right. When we take "up" as a rule, we constrain ourselves to a specific family of relations—those concerning ascension, elevation, altitude, and heights. Any spatial relations falling under these categories become part of our conceptual framework. Similarly with "down," we encounter concepts of descension, depth, and de-escalation.

What we're quantifying here is not these individual spatial modifications, but rather the general 'rules' from which they derive—that permanent form underlying all spatial perspectives of a certain class. This is the essence of quantification in spatial thinking.


Quantification in Practice


Quantification answers the crucial question of "how" we express ourselves within the spatio-temporal domain that rules of inference construct for us. It's not merely the spontaneous act of assertion but manifests when it judges according to, and in line with, the context of the rule.


Consider two profound examples:


When we assert that the Mariana Trench lies over five thousand fathoms below sea level, we're quantifying through the spatial concept of 'down.' Conversely, when we state that Mount Everest rises over eight thousand meters high, we're quantifying through the spatial concept of 'up.'


(x) → 'up' or. (x) → 'down'


The Kantian Perspective


These judgments align perfectly with Kant's conception if we consider 'down' or 'up' as universals in relation to the concepts tht fall under them. They exemplify universal quantification in its most fundamental sense. This represents a 'deictic' form of quantification—one that points or indicates— quantification nonetheless, as its foundation is inherently logical.


The Logical Foundation


A quantifier, in the logical sense, serves as the device through which we determine objects via the modes constructed by rules of inference (of thinking particulars under universals). Given our four fundamental rules of inference, we can infer the existence of four distinct quantifiers, each corresponding to a particular rule.



Note: The above approach reveals how our spatial understanding is deeply rooted in logical structures, even when dealing with seemingly straightforward concepts of direction and position. The beauty of this system lies in its ability to connect our immediate spatial experiences with deeper logical principles.


Conclusion


This exploration of spatial quantification demonstrates the profound connection between our basic spatial concepts and the underlying logical structures that give them meaning. Whether we're considering the depths of the ocean or the heights of mountains, we're engaging with a sophisticated system of logical quantification that shapes our understanding of the physical world.


Note: This analysis bridges the gap between immediate spatial experience and abstract logical thinking, revealing their intrinsic connection.

 
 
 

Comments


SUBSCRIBE VIA EMAIL

  • Facebook
  • Pinterest
  • Twitter
  • Instagram

© 2035 by Salt & Pepper. Powered and secured by Wix

bottom of page